Page images
PDF
EPUB

bind, and what sentences they are said to contain: and because by them we are to be judged in public, if questions do. arise, from them also we may take our rule in private. This seems reasonable: but on the other side, I find that lawyers themselves say otherwise; and I have seen Tiraquel much blamed, for quoting Bartholus, Baldus, and Salicetus " for the signification of the word ' mox,' by and by,' which is of use in this present rule: because though they were great lawyers, yet they were no good grammarians; and therefore that in these cases, Erasmus and Calepine, Valla and Linacre, Cicero and Terence, Priscian and Donatus, were the most competent judges. There is something on both sides, which is to weigh down each other, according as some other consideration shall determine. But therefore, as to the case of conscience, I shall give a better and surer rule than either one or other, or both: and that is,—

31. (7.) This being in matters of load and burden, by the consent of all men, the conscience and the guilty person are to be favoured as much as there can be cause for. Therefore whenever there is a dispute, whether the sentence of the law must be incurred presently, or that the sentence of the judge is to be expected; the presumption is always to be for ease, and for liberty, and favourable senses. Burdens are not to be imposed upon consciences without great evidence, and great necessity. If the lawyers differ in their opinions concerning the sentence, whether it be already made, or is to be made by the judge, let them first agree, and then let the conscience do as she sees reason. Thus if the word 'mox,' 'by and by,' be used in a sentence of law, because we find that in some very good authors it signifies with some interval of time (as in Cicero, "Discedo parumper à somniis : ad quæ mox revertar * ;" and " Præteriit villam meam Curio, jussitque mihi nunciari se mox venturum ""): therefore we may make use of it to our advantage, and suppose the conscience of a delinquent at liberty from a spontaneous execution of a sentence of law, if for that sentence he have no other sign, but that the word mox' is used in the law. "In pœnis benignior est interpretatio facienda," "In matters of punishment we are to take the easier part ;" and that is, to stay

Alph. à Castro lib. 2. de Leg. Poen. cap. 7.

De Divin. i. c. 23. Davis. Rath. pag. 61.

y Ad Attic. x. 4.

from being punished as long as we can

and in proportion

to this, Panormitan gives this rule e; "When the words of the law signify the time past, or the time to come, we are to understand it in the more favourable sense; and that it includes the sentence of the judge, before which the criminal is not obliged. And to this very purpose the words of infinite and indefinite signification are to be expounded; and this answers many cases of conscience, and brings peace in more; and the thing being reasonable, peaceful, and consonant to the common opinion of the lawyers, ought to pass for a just conclusion and determination of conscience.

32. (8.) After all, as there is ease to the criminal, so there must be care of the law; and therefore when a law imposes a punishment which would prove invalid, to no purpose and of no effect, unless it be of present force upon the committing of fact, it is to be concluded, the law intends it for a sententia lata à jure,' that it presently obliges the conscience of the guilty person. The reason is, because it cannot be supposed that the law should do a thing to no purpose, and therefore must intend so to oblige as that the sin be punished. If therefore to expect the sentence of the judge would wholly evacuate the penalty, or make it insufficient to do the purpose and intention of the law; the sentence of the law must be suffered by the guilty person without the judge. And this is true, however the words of law be used, whether in the past, present, or future time, whether simply or by reduplication, whether imperatively or infinitely: such are the penalties of infamy, irregularity, nullity of actions or contracts, especially if they be of such contracts, which if they once prove valid, are so for ever, as in the contract of marriage. And therefore if a law be made that a man shall not marry her, whom, in her husband's lifetime, he had polluted: this must be supposed to be meant of nullifying the contract before it is consummate; that is, it is a sentence which the criminal must execute upon himself: for if he does not, but' de facto' marries the adulteress, and consummates the marriage, it will be too late to complain to the judge; for he cannot annul the contract afterward.

* Cap. in Pœnis de Reg. Jur. lib. 6.

RULE III.

Penalties imposed by the Judge must be suffered and submitted to; but may not, after such Sentence, be inflicted by the Hands of the condemned.

1. THE first part of this rule hath in it but little difficulty; for there is only in it this variety: In all punishments that are tolerable, that is, all but death, dismembering, or intolerable and extremely disgraceful scourgings, and grievous and sickly imprisonments, we owe not only obedience to the laws, but reverence and honour; because whatsoever is less than these, may, without sin, and without indecency, and without great violations of our natural love and rights, be inflicted and suffered.

2. But the other evils are such, as are intolerable in civil and natural account; and every creature declines death, and the addresses and preparations to it, with so much earnestness, that it would be very unnatural and inhuman not to allow to condemned persons a civil and moral power of hating and declining death, and avoiding it in all means of natural capacity and opportunity. A man may, if he can, redeem his life with money, but he must not corrupt justice; a man may run from prison if he can, but to do it he must not kill the jailer; he may escape death, but he must not fight with the ministers of justice; he may run away, but he must not break his word; that is, he may do what is in his natural capacity to avoid these violences and extremities of nature, but nothing that is against a moral duty. "Non peccat quisquam, cum evitat supplicium, sed cum facit aliquid dignum supplicio;"" He that avoids his punishment, sins not, provided that in so doing he act nothing else worthy of punishment:" so St. Austin a.

3. This relies also upon a tacit or implicit permission of law; for in sentences given by judges, and to be executed by the ministers of law, the condemned person is not commanded; nor yet trusted with the execution, and it is wholly committed to ministers of purpose: and therefore the law supposes the condemned person infinitely unwilling, and lays bars, restraints, guards, and observators, upon him; from all which

a Lib. de Mendac. cap. 13.

if he can escape, he hath done no more than what the lawgiver supposed he was willing to do, and from which he did not restrain him by laws, but by force. But if to fly from prison, or to decline any other sentence, be expressly forbidden in the law, or if it be against his promise, or if a distinct penalty be annexed to such escapings, then it is plain that the law intends to oblige the conscience, for the law cannot punish what is no sin; it is in this case a transgression of the law, and therefore not lawful. But because the law hath no punishment greater than death, it cannot but be lawful for a condemned man to escape from prison if he can, because the law hath no punishment to establish a law against flying from prison after the sentence of death. And if it be said, that if a prisoner who flies, be taken, he hath more irons and more guards upon him, and worse usage in the prison; that is matter of caution, not punishment, at least not of law: for as for the jailer's spite and anger, his cruelty and revenge, himself alone is to give accounts.

4. But now for the other part of the rule, there is some more difficulty; which is caused by the great example of some great and little persons, who to prevent a death by the hand of their enemies, with the additions of shame and torment, have laid violent hands upon themselves. So did Zeno° and Chrysippus, Cleanthes and Empedocles, Euphrates the philosopher, and Demosthenes, Cato Uticensis, and Porcius Latro, Aristarchus and Anaxagoras, Cornelius Rufus and Silius Italicus. The Indians esteemed it the most glorious way of dying, as we find in Strabo, Olympiodorus o, and Porphyryf; and Eusebius tells, that most of the Germans did use to hang themselves. And, amongst the Romans, they that out of shame of being in debt, or impatience of grief, killed themselves, might make their wills, and after death they stood; "manebant testamenta, pretium festinandi," saith Tacitus, that was "the price of their making haste. Plato * discoursing of this question, said, Οὐ μέντοι ἴσως βιάσεται αύτόν· οὐ γὰρ φασὶ θεμιτὸν εἶναι, “ Peradventure a man must not do violence to himself, for they say it is not lawful." Upon this Olympiodorus discoursing on these words, reckons five cases b Vide Diogen. Laert. in Zenon.-Alexander Aphrodis. in 2. de Anima.--Lucian. in Macrob.-Galen. 5. de Loc. Affect.-Plutarch. in Pericle.-Suidas.-Plin. lib. 1. ep. 12. d In Phædon. Platon. Phæd. Fischer, c. 5. p. 252.

e

Περὶ φιλοψυχ. 4.

c Lib. 15.
1 Annal. 6.

in which the Stoics held it lawful to kill themselves. 1. For public good; 2. For private necessity, to avoid a tyrant's snare; 3. In cases of natural madness; 4. When the body is intolerably afflicted; 5. and lastly, In extreme poverty. And the Greeks commended a Pythagorean woman, who being asked why she and her sect did not eat beans, she said, she would rather eat them than tell: but being commanded by a tyrant to eat them, she said, she would rather tell than eat them but in fine she cut out her tongue, because she would neither taste nor tell. Thus Seneca tells of a prisoner, that being to be exposed to beasts in the theatre, he broke his neck in the spondyls of the wheel upon which he was drawn to the spectacles; and of another that died by a pertinacious holding of his breath. But that of Sampson, and Saul, and Razis, are also brought into example; and are alleged to prove, that a man may, a few hours or days, hasten his death, if, by so doing, he takes the lighter part. St. Chrysostomi tells of St. Pelagia: "Pelagia virgo, quindecim annos nata, sponte sibi necem maturavit: parata quidem erat ad cruciatus tormentaque et omne suppliciorum genus perferendum: sed metuebat tamen ne virginitatis coronam perderet:" "Being a virgin of fifteen years of age, of her own accord she hastened death unto herself; she was indeed ready to have suffered all sorts of most exquisite torments, but she was not willing to lose the crown of her virginity." Upon which fact of hers, he thus discourses; "Hence you may perceive, that the lust of the wicked hangmen struck fear into Pelagia, and therefore from their injurious lust the maiden removed and snatched herself: for if she might have kept the crown of her virginity, and receive the crown of martyrdom besides, she would not have refused the judgmentseat; but because it was altogether necessary to lose the one of them, she had a just cause, by her own voluntary death, to prevent so great an injury.”—And St. Ambrose writing to his sister Marcellina, expressly commends those virgin-martyrs, who, to prevent their ravishments, did hasten their death by voluntary precipices, or drowning; and particularly allows the fact of Pelagia. To which I add also, St. Jerome', who,

b Epist. 70. 20. Ruhkopf, vol. 2. pag. 331.

¡Vide Front. Ducæum tom. 1. S. Chrysost. n. 628.

k

* Lib. 3. de Virgin. In cap. 1. Jonæ, in hæc verba, Mittite me in mare.

« PreviousContinue »